Home

Syllabus

Lecture Topics

Homework

Test Solutions

Policies


Math 4820: History of Mathematical Ideas, Spring 2013


Lecture Topics


Date
What we discussed/How we spent our time
Jan 14
Syllabus. Text. We discussed CE/BCE notation for dating. (No year zero.) We discussed a coarse timeline of development for Homo sapiens. We discussed some of the the earliest mathematical objects/writings, namely:

The Ishango bone:    
Plimpton 322:    
The Rhind papyrus:    
The Moscow papyrus:    

Jan 16
We discussed an early solution method for quadratic equations. We gave two proofs of the Pythagorean Theorem: one attributed to Pythagoras and Euclid's "Bride's Chair" proof. We defined Pythagorean triples.
Jan 18
We gave proofs of the Pythagorean Theorem attributed to Thabit ibn Qurra, Da Vinci and Garfield. We started discussing the chord and tangent method for parametrizing rational points on the circle. (We established that every rational point on the circle has the form ((1-t2)/(1+t2),2t/(1+t2)) for some rational t.)
Jan 23
We showed how to derive the formula for Pythagorean triples from the parametrization of rational points on the circle. Quiz 1 with 98 different solutions.
Jan 25
We briefly discussed Hippasus, who is said to have been drowned for divulging some mathematical secret, then turned to commensurable numbers. We defined segments a and b to be commensurable if there is a segment c and positive whole numbers m and n such that |a| = m*|c|, |b| = n*|c|. We mentioned that a and b are commensurable iff the ratio of their lengths is a rational number. We proved √2 is irrational by reductio ad absurdum.
Jan 28
We introduced and justified the Euclidean algorithm for finding the gcd of two positive whole numbers. We gave a geometric version of the algorithm and explained how it could be used to determine the commensurability of two lengths. (Construct an a×b rectangle and repeatedly delete maximal square subregions. The algorithm terminates iff a and b are commensurable.) We used this algorithm to show that the Golden Ratio, φ=(1+√5)/2, is not rational. Quiz 2.
Jan 30
We discussed continued fractions and the Golden Ratio.
Feb 1
Classification of polyhedra 1: We discussed
1. the Platonic solids (= convex polyhedra whose sides are congruent regular polygons and which have the same number of sides meeting at each vertex),
2. the prisms, antiprisms, and Archimedean solids (= convex polyhedra not of type 1. whose sides are regular polygons which meet at each vertex in the same vertex configuration), and
3. the Johnson solids (= convex polyhedra not of types 1. or 2. whose sides are regular polygons which meet in a strictly convex way at each vertex).
We stated that there are 5 Platonic solids, infinitely many prisms and antiprisms, either 13 or 15 Archimedean solids, and 92 Johnson solids.

We mentioned that the Platonic solids have been identified with the classical elements: tetrahedron=fire, cube=earth, octahedron=air, icosahedron=water, dodecahedron=aether.
We began a proof that there are only 5 Platonic solids. So far we have introduced Euler's formula: v-e+f=2, and the relations pf=2e=qv, for a regular polyhedron of type (p,q). (A regular polyhedron has type (p,q) if its faces are regular p-gons with q of them meeting at each vertex.)

Feb 4
Classification of polyhedra 2: We showed that a regular polyhedron of type (p,q) -- meaning all faces are congruent regular p-gons with q meeting at each vertex -- has the following properties:
1. (p,q)=(3,3), (3,4), (4,3), (3,5), or (5,3).
2. (v,e,f) = (4p/(2p+2q-pq),2pq/(2p+2q-pq),4q/(2p+2q-pq)) Quiz 3.
Feb 6
Classification of polyhedra 3: We wrapped up the discussion of the problem of classifying the regular polyhedra, indicating that after obtaining the numerical characteristics of the regular polyhedra one can argue by cases that only 5 are possible. To show that 5 exist, we must construct them. We gave ad hoc arguments for the tetrahedron and cube, Pacioli's argument for the icosahedron, and then obtained the octahedron and dodecahedron by duality. We then traced some of the influence on modern mathematics that developed from this classification problem, namely the Euler characteristic, Descartes' Theorem about the total defect of a polyhedron, and the Gauss-Bonnet Theorem.
Feb 8
The Greek construction problems 1: We discussed straightedge and compass constructions. We briefly indicated how to construct a line through two points at opposite ends of the galaxy using ordinary-size straightedge and compass. We gave recursive definitions of "constructible point", "constructible line", "constructible circle"; all other constructible objects are defined in terms of these. We showed how to construct:
1. an equilateral triangle,
2. a line through a give point perpendicular to a give line,
3. a line through a given point parallel to a given line,
4. an angle bisector and a segment n-sector,
5. a regular pentagon.
Feb 11
The Greek construction problems 2: We discussed four of the classical Greek construction problems: squaring the circle, doubling the cube, trisecting a general angle and contructing a regular n-gon. Then we began discussing how to "algebraize" plane geometry by introducing coordinates. Quiz 4.
Feb 13
The Greek construction problems 3: We continued our discussion of the coordinatization of affine plane geometries. We noted that the smallest affine plane has four points {O, I, C, D} and six lines {{O,I},{O,C},{O,D},{I,C},{I,D},{C,D}}, and that the associated number system has 2 elements. We noted that the set of constructible points and lines in the Euclidean plane is an affine plane, hence has an associated number system. We labeled it E0 and called it the field of of constructible real numbers. We stated that E0 is the smallest subfield of the real numbers that is closed under square roots of positive numbers.

We spoke about HW problem #1, and argued that if a regular pentagon of side length x can be inscribed in a circle of radius 1, then x must equal √(2-2cos(72°)). We also argued that cos(72°)=1/(2φ). Thus, HW problem #1 reduces to the problem of showing that the side length of the inscribed pentagon is √(2-1/φ).

Feb 15
The Greek construction problems 4: We gave examples and nonexamples of fields, ordered fields and Euclidean fields. We described the field ℚ[√2] that is obtained from ℚ by adjoining √2. We began a discussion of why the field E0 of constructible numbers is the smallest Euclidean subfield of ℝ. The most interesting step in showing that E0 is Euclidean was the step showing how to construct the square root of a positive number with straightedge and compass.

We ended the lecture by defining, for any Euclidean subfield E of ℝ, the set of E-points, E-lines and E-circles of the plane, and posed the problems of showing that a line through two E-points is an E-line, the circle centered at an E-point through another E-point is an E-circle, and a point of intersection of two E-lines, two E-circles or an E-line and an E-circle is an E-point.

Feb 18
The Greek construction problems 5: We showed that if E is a Euclidean subfield of ℝ, then it is closed under straightedge and compass constructions. As a consequence we obtain that the field of constructible real numbers is the smallest Euclidean subfield of ℝ. Quiz 5 without solutions. Quiz 5 with solutions.
Feb 20
The Greek construction problems 6:
Theorem. r is a real constructible number if and only if there is a finite chain of subfields F0⊆…⊆Fk such that
(i) F0=ℚ,
(ii) Fi+1= Fi[√p] for some p∈ Fi+, and
(iii) Fk contains r.

Theorem. If r is a constructible real number, then r is algebraic and minr,ℚ(x) has degree that is a power of 2.

Theorem. (Lindemann, 1882) π is transcendental.

Corollary. √π is transcendental. Hence it is impossible to square a general circle with straightedge and compass. (Some circles can be squared, but not all. For example, a unit circle cannot be squared.)

We showed that the problem of constructing a cube with twice the volume of a given one reduces to the problem of determining if the cube root of 2 is constructible. The lecture ended without resolving the problem of determining whether x3-2 is the minimal polynomial of the cube root of 2.

Feb 22
The Greek construction problems 7:
We considered the problem of how to determine the minimal polynomial of an algebraic number. We argued that:
1. Minimal polynomials are irreducible over the rational numbers.
2. A monic polynomial irreducible over the rationals is the minimal polynomial for any of its roots.
3. The rational root theorem is sufficient to help determine the irreducibility of a rational cubic.
We used these facts to show that x3-2 is the minimal polynomial of the cube root of 2, and hence it is not possible to double the unit cube with straightedge and compass.

We then turned to the problem of trisecting a general angle, and I introduced the polynomial:
x3 - 3x - 2cos(α),
which is a monic polynomial that has x=2cos(α/3) as a root. When α=60°, 2cos(α)=2cos(60°)=1, and the rational root theorem applies to show that x3 - 3x - 1 is the minimal polynomial of x=2cos(α/3)=2cos(20°). Since 2cos(60°) is constructible and 2cos(20°) is not, it is not possible to trisect a 60° angle with straightedge and compass.

Feb 25
The Greek construction problems 8:
We discussed a procedure for finding a monic rational polynomial (in fact, an integer polynomial) p(x) of degree n such that x=2cos(α/n) is a root of p(x)-2cos(α)=0. Quiz 6.
Feb 27
Midterm review.
Mar 1
Midterm.
Mar 4
Section 3.4. We discussed Archimedes' cattle problem, which reduces to an instance of Pell's equation. We mentioned how Bhaskara II used Bramhagupta's Identity to describe an algorithm for solving Pell's equation. We explained how to use continued fractions to find a fundamental solution, and then how to use the fundamental solution to generate all other solutions.
Mar 6
Read Chapter 4. We discussed the method of exhaustion, and used it to establish the area formula of a circle.
Mar 8
Read Chapter 4. We discussed how to use exhaustion to find a formula for computing the area of a parabolic sector. The proof involved exhaustion in two ways: once to approximate the area by triangles, and the second time to compute the sum
1+(1/4)+(1/42)+(1/43)+…
Mar 11
We completed the last detail of Archimedes' quadrature of the parabola. Then we worked on a handout concerning Pell's equation.
Mar 13
Quiz 7. We discussed the discovery of the cubic formula.
Mar 15
We derived the cubic formula. We discussed the polar form for complex numbers, and used it to give a geometric interpretation of multiplication. We discussed roots of unity, ω = cos(2π/n)+i*sin(2π/n). Finally we discussed how cube roots of unity are used to express all three roots of x3+px+q=0.
Mar 18
We discussed Viete's Formulas, which relate the coefficients of a polynomial to its roots. Then we discussed how to "depress" a polynomial. Finally, we started deriving the quartic formula. Quiz 8.
Mar 20
We finished discussing the quartic formula. We then turned to higher degree equations, noting that Tschirnhaus developed a way of depressing monic nth degree polynomials to eliminate the (n-1)rst and (n-2)nd degree terms, and Bring advanced the procedure for quintics to eliminate the 4rth, 3rd and 2nd degree terms. We defined Bring radicals and stated that the roots of an arbitrary quintic are expressible in terms of arithmetic operations, rationals, root extraction and Bring radicals. We discussed the work of Ruffini, Abel and Galois on the unsolvability of the general nth degree equation, n≥5.
Mar 22
We discussed the problem of determining the number of points of intersection of two plane curves defined by polynomial equations P(x,y)=0 and Q(x,y)=0. We stated Bezout's Theorem, that the number of intersection points is deg(P)*deg(Q), provided the number of intersection points is counted "properly". In particular, we restrict attention to the situation where the polynomials P and Q have no common factor, and then we have to consider intersection points with complex coordinates, we have to count intersection points with the proper multiplicity, and we have to count "intersection points at infinity". During the last half of the lecture we discussed how compute the intersection multiplicity Ip(P,Q).
Apr 1
We reviewed Bezout's Theorem and the definition of intersection multiplicity. We calculated I(a,b)(P,Q) for some examples. We then defined the projective plane as the object obtained from the Euclidean plane by adding one point at infinity for each parallel line family and one new line consisting of all points at infinity.
Apr 3
We discussed the construction of the projective plane by adding a line at infinity and also the construction through homogeneous coordinates. For the first construction, we showed that the construction also works for other affine planes, and drew a picture of the Fano plane (which is the projective plane obtained from the 4-element affine plane by adding a line at infinity).
Apr 5
We discussed the equations for polynomial curves in the projective plane. We observed that the homogenizations of y-x2 and of xy-1 are the same up to a permutation of variables, suggesting that parabolas and hyperbolas are look the same in the projective plane. We gave a geometric argument explaining why all irreducible conics look like the circle in the projective plane. We found the points at infinity on y=x2 and xy=1. We ended by describing how projective transformations may be represented by matrices, and how the columns of the matrix may be found by looking at the image of the triangle with vertices [1:0:0], [0:1:0], [0:0:1].
Apr 8
We started the classification of quadratic curves in the real projective plane. The bulk of this lecture was spent in explaining why invertible 3×3-matrices represent collineations. We stated the classification theorem: a subset of the real projective plane that is defined by a homogeneous quadratic polynomial is projectively equivalent to a circle, a pair of lines (possibly equal), a single point, or the empty set. (The last 2 possibilities do not occur in the complex projective plane.) Quiz 9.
Apr 10
We showed that any homogeneous quadratic polynomial whose zero set does not lie entirely on a line defines a set that is projectively equivalent to a circle or to a pair of distinct lines.

I reset the HW due date from this Friday to next Monday.

Apr 12
We proved Pascal's Theorem.
Apr 15
We worked on this collaborative project.
Apr 19
We discussed the discovery of hyperbolic geometry and started describing the Poincare model of the hyperbolic plane.
Apr 22
We discussed reflection through hyperbolic lines in the Poincare model (via circular inversion) and showed that any point in the Poincare model can be moved to any other point using 1 or 2 reflections. Quiz 11.
Apr 24
We explained why the first four of Euclid's axioms hold in the Poincare model while the fifth one fails. We mentioned that hyperbolic geometry is a rich and strange geometry in which angle sums of triangles are always less than 180 degrees and where the Pythagorean Theorem takes an unusual form.

We discussed the idea of "bi-interpretable" structures, and gave as an example the real number field and the complex number field equipped with complex conjugation. The Poincare model is an interpretation of hyperbolic plane geometry into Euclidean plane geometry. I mentioned that there is an interpretation in the reverse direction, so that in fact Euclidean geometry and hyperbolic geometry are bi-interpretable. This means that a fact about one of the geometries is equivalent to a fact about the other (possibly expressed in a different way). In particular, the two geometries are equiconsistent.

We then turned to area, noting that (whether in the Euclidean plane or the hyperbolic plane) area ought to be a function α defined at least on unions of triangles such that (i) α(R)>0 if R has nonempty interior, (ii) α(T1)=α(T2) if T1 and T2 are congruent triangles, and (iii) α(P∪Q)=α(P)+α(Q) if the intersection of P and Q has empty interior. We mentioned that this determines area on unions of triangles up to a normalizing factor: in the Euclidean plane it determines an area function whose values on rectangles are given by base×height, while in the hyperbolic plane it determines an area function whose vlaues on triangles are give by defect.

Apr 26
We discussed equidecomposability of polygons in the plane. We started the proof of the Wallace-Bolyai-Gerwien Theorem, and completed all except the proof that any rectangle is equidecomposable with a square of the same area.
Apr 29
We completed the proof of the W-B-G Theorem about equidecomposability in the plane. Quiz 12.
May 1
We discussed the first three of Hilbert's problems, and explained to what degree they have been resolved: the Continuum Hypothesis, the problem of determining the consistency of arithmetic, and the equidecomposability of polyhedra. (With regard to the third problem, we described the Banach-Tarski paradox.) The bulk of the lecture was devoted to the third problem, in particular to defining the Dehn invariant and sketching the proof that if P and Q are equidecomposable polyhedra, then P and Q must have the same volume and the same Dehn invariant. We calculated the Dehn invariant of a cube to be zero. We identified two tetrahedra with equal bases and heights but different Dehn invariants. I distributed a review sheet for the final.
May 3
We reviewed for the final.